perm filename OBJEC.TEX[ESS,JMC] blob
sn#870908 filedate 1989-03-07 generic text, type C, neo UTF8
COMMENT ā VALID 00002 PAGES
C REC PAGE DESCRIPTION
C00001 00001
C00002 00002 \chapter{22}{Mathematics and Objectivity in Human Affairs}
C00019 ENDMK
Cā;
\chapter{22}{Mathematics and Objectivity in Human Affairs}
Consider the following extreme example of a desirable future
state of affairs. A super-smart high school student gets the idea
that the U.S. admit foreign tourists without visas to reduce red tape
and promote good will.
He sits down at his trusty computer console and asks for a
description of the present policy and its rationalization. Back
comes a set of sentences in a formal but readable language. The
rationalization is a pseudo-proof that the policy is in the best
interests of the country and is in accordance with the currently
accepted principles of justice. A pseudo-proof is like a proof except
that it contains steps wherein something that has been asserted to be
plausible is assumed.) SSHSS does not believe the pseudo-proof and
after much labor discovers that one of the assumptions or
pseudo-steps is not valid and succeeds in making a pseudo-proof that
his proposed policy is better than the official one. The computer
proof checker accepts his pseudo-proof, and the public information
system tells him that the relevant official is the head of the
Immigration Service. Next morning the head of the Immigration
Service is informed by his console that someone he has never heard of
has proved that his policy in this area ought to be changed. This
does not happen very often, and he is rather annoyed because all
previous policy changes in this area have come as a result of the
work of his staff. Nevertheless, he has to pay attention to the
proposal, because there is a policy that if a government official
ignores a computer checked pseudo-proof that his policy should be
changed for a month, the request for change goes up a level in the
hierarchy. Therefore, he has his staff examine the assumptions of
the argument carefully, and after a while everyone is convinced that
the new assumptions are more plausible than the old, and the policy
is changed.
This happy scenario is based on the future achievement of
several goals some of which are rather distant:
\item{1.} There is a formalism in which facts about policies and
there effects can be expressed, and which allows conclusions to be
drawn about the relative merit of different policies.
\item{2.} The criteria that determine whether one state of affairs
is socially better than another are agreed upon and formalized to a
sufficient extent.
\item{3.} There is sufficient public confidence in the above to
cause government use of the formal methods.
\item{4.} The existing policies are formally described and formal
arguments justifying them are publicly available.
\item{5.} The technique for manipulating the formalism is widely
understood by people who want to affect policy.
\noindent If these goals are met, it will have the following good
effects:
\item{1.} Anyone who feels offended by a policy even esthetically
can know precisely what it is and why it is thought to be correct.
\item{2.} If he can show formally that some other policy would be
better, officials will pay attention. This depends on the formal
system acting as a filter so that the policy making officials will
not be overloaded with half-baked ideas. On the other hand, getting
official attention will not depend on his status in society.
\noindent Let us compare this desired state of affairs with the present
state of affairs in our society. The degree of objectivity of
policies depends on the subject matter, and the number of people who
can affect the policy is greater, the greater the objectivity of the
matter.
\item{1.} The most objective are is the body of theorems of
mathematics. Anyone can submit a paper to a mathematical journal. The
referees of a paper are not supposed to pay attention to the status
of the writer and often referee papers written by people they have
never heard of. There are many journals, and if one rejects it, the
author can submit it to another. Once a paper is published, it will
affect the mathematical ideas of the time. Almost all published
mathematical theorems are correct, and controversy over whether
something has been proved is rare. On the other hand, whether a
mathematical result is important is not an objective affair, and it
certainly happens that important results are ignored for some time.
It is also important to note that the only equipment required for
mathematical work is paper and pencil and access to a library. To
make a living doing mathematics requires an academic job, but there
are very few scandals where someone unable to get such a job was
found many years later to have done first class work which was
ignored. There are a number of success stories like Ramanujan's
where someone in an obscure position was found to have done first
class work and brought into a first class environment. Moreover,
every year there are cases in which someone gets a full professorship
(ordinarily obtained in one's thirties or forties) in his early
twenties.
\noindent This situation is not a consequence of some superior
virtuousness of mathematicians. Rather it is a consequence of the
objectivity of merit in mathematics. It also exists in athletics and
in chess (Fischer became U.S. champion at the age of 14 and was
thereby recognized as an expert).
\item{2.} The situation is almost as good in physics and chemistry.
However, the possibility of verifying an idea may depend on the
facilities for making experiments, and this may depend on the
reputation of the person proposing the idea.
\item{3.} In engineering the matter is still more difficult because
the ability to try out ideas is even more expensive. Nevertheless,
there are large areas of engineering that are quite uncontroversial,
because it can be objectively calculated whether something will work
or not even if it is not so clear which of several methods that will
work is the best.
\item{4.}Once we come to social ideas, the situation is much worse.
Getting an idea tried depends on achieving political power. Even
after the ideas is tried, whether it is any good is still
controversial. The proposer can claim that it is someone else's
fault that things worked out badly.
\noindent The prevailing opinion is probably that this situation is
inevitable. In fact, some people proceed from the difficulty of
deciding social questions to claim that engineering, physics and
mathematics are not objective either. I would like to express the
reverse view: economics, sociology, history, and politics are
possible, but difficult sciences. They have made little progress
except for economics, and the future sciences in these fields will
ascribe little merit to present or past ideas in these subjects.
However, the future will be better
Another necessary component of the objectification of social
decisions is the development of formal reasoning and its application
to non-mathematical contexts. This problem has been clarified by
work in artificial intelligence and great progress can be expected in
the next decades. Within five years formal proof may become an
accepted tool form establishing the correctness of computer programs,
then it will be extended to proving that computer systems meet their
specifications including systems that interact with the outside
world. Then it will become possible to determine when a social theory
actually predicts the result of a policy and to determine the
predicted result. This will allow the social sciences to make much
more rapid progress than heretofore.
\vfill\eject
\section{22.1}{Remarks}
\item{1.} The most extensive effort to make a general scientific
theory including philosophy and all the social sciences was Marxism.
It failed, but we have to try again and again until we succeed. If
10,000 years goes without success, it may be time to give up.
Nevertheless, we have to remain skeptical about the claims of any
particular attempt and avoid wishful thinking. The arguments for a
social principle of complementarity analogous the Heisenberg
principle in physics represent mere wishful thinking on the part of
obscurantists discouraged by the difficulties of social science into
trying to prove such a science impossible.
\item{2.} Present attempts to simulate complex social events on
computers are almost all too simplified to be useful. The formalisms
are inadequate to express the kinds of knowledge people actually
have.
\item{3.} Some technical ideas relevant to this goal of
objectification are discussed in the paper ``Some Philosophical
Problems from the Standpoint of Artificial Intelligence'' in Machine
Intelligence 4, Edinburgh University Press 1969.
\item{4.}The foregoing is not presented as a complete argument. It
is more aimed at encouraging others inclined to think in this way
than to convince the unconvinced.
\noindent To what extent is it possible to extend the objectivity
of mathematics to science, engineering and human affairs?
First: What do we mean by objectivity? Consider that when someone
makes a mathematical assertion, he is expected to prove it. The
mathematical literature publishes thousands of pages annually of
new mathematical assertions and their proofs. Mathematical proof
is an extremely reliable process. Less than one in a thousand
of published mathematical assertions are later found to be mistaken
or even occasion any controversy. In popular fields of mathematics
where people check each others work controversy over what has been
proved is almost non-existent. (There is plenty of controversy
over what is useful, important, or beautiful in mathematics).
This objectivity of mathematics has some important useful
consequences. Namely, anyone who has an idea for improving
mankind's state of mathematical knowledge can write a paper
and submit it to a journal. The process by which publication
\vfill\eject